SPECIAL ARTICLE
The Logic of Clinical Reasoning in
Medicine
Federico Alfano,* Daniel Moya**
*Clínica
Universidad de Navarra, Pamplona, Spain
**Orthopedics
and Traumatology Department, Hospital Británico de Buenos Aires, Autonomous
City of Buenos Aires, Argentina.
ABSTRACT
Three modes of inference underpin clinical
reasoning: abduction, deduction, and induction. Abduction generates plausible
explanations or diagnostic hypotheses at the outset of evaluation. Deduction
guides the selection of tests to probe the consequences of those hypotheses and
to assess whether the presumptive diagnosis accounts for all clinical findings.
Induction then compares the hypotheses’ predictions with observable facts to
determine whether the expected findings are indeed present.
Keywords: Medical
diagnosis; clinical reasoning; critical thinking.
Level of Evidence: V
La lógica del criterio clínico médico
RESUMEN
Los tres tipos de razonamiento que conforman
el criterio clínico de los médicos son la abducción, la deducción y la
inducción. La abducción se utiliza para generar explicaciones o hipótesis
posibles al principio del proceso diagnóstico. El razonamiento deductivo se
utiliza para determinar qué pruebas deben realizarse para explorar las
consecuencias de las hipótesis y luego preguntarse si realmente el diagnóstico
presuntivo explica todos los hallazgos. La fase inductiva compara las
afirmaciones de la hipótesis con los hechos observables para finalmente evaluar
si están presentes o no los hallazgos esperados.
Palabras clave:
Diagnóstico médico; razonamiento clínico; pensamiento crítico.
Nivel de Evidencia: V
INTRODUCTION
Reaching
a definitive diagnosis in a patient is a complex phenomenon because it involves
dynamic and incomplete information. To address this, physicians use logic,
evidence-based medical knowledge, and clinical experience to arrive at a
diagnosis through a structured process.1
This process is analytical and systematic and combines scientific aspects with
deductive and inductive reasoning skills. This formula, known as the hypothesis
method, consists of choosing one hypothesis among several alternatives.2 More than a mere part of our medical
legacy or an interesting historical and philosophical vestige, the hypothesis
method is the cornerstone of diagnostic reasoning. In Phaedo, Plato formulated
for the first time the hypothetical method that consists of choosing one
hypothesis over other alternatives.3
Undoubtedly, critical thinking predates clinical judgment.
Critical
thinking is the cognitive tool used to analyze knowledge. Its application in
medicine is called clinical reasoning. It requires both knowledge of disease
and familiarity with the particular patient’s clinical context, since critical
thinking is used to discern and interpret both the scientific evidence and the
patient’s presentation.
The
diagnostic process, like practicing a surgical approach, is always trainable
and improvable. A long career is not a guarantee of good practice or savoir faire. It is an
error to confuse experience with expertise and expert performance. The
latter implies the correct interpretation of the available information and,
therefore, proper execution. The logic of expertise cannot stand on its own; it
must be articulated between scientific evidence and the
information we obtain from our patients. The objectivity of scientific evidence
is fundamental, since formal logic deals with the rules that govern inferences
and focuses on the structure of arguments, but not on the truth of their
premises. In the end, logic concerns itself with the structures and laws that govern
meanings and relations among propositions, but it cannot go beyond these.
In most
cases, well-trained subspecialists can reach the correct diagnosis with little
effort using deductive reasoning alone. However, although pattern recognition
can be an essential part of the deductive process, relying on it exclusively is
likely to lead to diagnostic errors in less common diseases. Stereotyped
diagnosis limits us to skill only in what is common,
much like grandmothers who could recognize teething-related diarrhea in an
infant.
To use
deductive reasoning with minimal error, we must be aware of the logical
fallacies into which the diagnostic process may fall. Correct diagnoses rest on
valid reasoning as well as correct information. The shoulder specialist who
disregards logic may naively assume that a diagnosis has been proven when, in reality, it has only been shown to be possible or probable.
Knowing the logical basis of proof and refutation should help us not only to be
more accurate in individual diagnosis, but also to provide a rational approach
to developing diagnostic criteria supported by Evidence-Based Medicine.
The
purpose of this article is to review the hypothesis method as it applies to
medical diagnosis and to the application of clinical judgment.
FIRST IMPRESSION AND ABDUCTIVE
REASONING
The
expression abductive reasoning (or abductive judgment) refers to a form of
logical reasoning that physicians (and others) use to formulate explanatory
hypotheses based on incomplete observations. The concept was introduced and
developed by the American philosopher and logician Charles Sanders Peirce and
is defined as the process of inferring the best possible explanation from the
available data.4
When the
patient states the chief complaint, we can abduct from this history the
possible causes and the etiopathogenesis of the illness. To achieve this, we
resort to abductive judgment, because deductive and inductive reasoning by
themselves are insufficient to explain and infer what occurs during the initial
stage of the diagnostic process, when the physician must generate potential
diagnoses and their possible causes, given that the information available
cannot yet contribute to the development of explanatory theories. Abduction, as
a form of creative inference, is used instead to generate possible explanations
or hypotheses through the analysis of incomplete observations at the outset of
the diagnostic process.
Abductive
judgment rests on conditional probability, namely the probability that
something occurs given that something else has already occurred. In practical
terms, if a patient reports a fall from a bicycle and presents with a deformity
of the clavicle, a fracture of that bone is to be expected. The analysis then
proceeds to the recognition of key elements or sets of elements, such as
“shoulder pain” or “active loss of mobility.” In this way, the formulation of
abductive reasoning builds the foundations that will guide the next step in the
process: deduction.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING
After the
first impression furnished by abduction, the physician lists possible
differential diagnoses; the scientist, hypotheses; and the detective, suspected
criminals. Each recognizes that most hypotheses are incorrect and that the work
consists in eliminating the incorrect ones and confirming the correct ones, two
complementary yet very different processes. For example, the detective uses an alibi for elimination and motive or evidence of presence
at the scene, or both, for incrimination. The scientist proposes a hypothesis,
defines its implications, and then designs experiments based on these
deductions. If the experiment confirms expectations, the hypothesis is
supported. If the experimental results contradict the hypothesis, that
hypothesis must be abandoned. On this point, José Manuel del Sel5wrote: “… Hypotheses in science are always
conditioned by being refutable; unfavorable evidence must be sought
conscientiously. The scientist does not try, nor does he grow upset if his
theory is refuted, because it would be much worse to persist if it is
fraudulent …”
Findings that are merely compatible do not affirm a
diagnosis; they simply establish that it is possible. Conversely, if our
presumptive diagnosis fails to explain the findings that emerge from the
physical examination, it is likely because the diagnostic hypothesis has been
incorrect, that is, the abductive reasoning has failed. In such a case, either
we lack knowledge about the possible diseases the patient may have, or our
history taking and initial assessment have been inadequate, or we have too hastily
discarded other differential diagnoses.
Deductive
reasoning is used to determine which tests should be performed to explore the
consequences of the hypotheses. It applies a known general rule to a particular
case. Here, we assume a hypothesis is possible, and the examiner must decide
which clinical tests and ancillary studies are necessary to confirm or refute
it. If predicted and observed results match, the hypothesis is supported but
not confirmed, unless the examination findings are specific to that disease. If
the findings cannot be explained by our diagnostic hypothesis, the hypothesis is rejected (Figure 1).
INDUCTIVE REASONING
The
physician tests each hypothetical diagnosis in turn, attempting to refute the
incorrect and to prove the correct. To do so, two elementary questions are
posed: does the diagnosis explain all the clinical findings,
and are the expected findings present? If these findings are specific to
the disease, we have reached a definitive diagnosis (Figure
2).
To answer
the first question, we examine the particular case (the illness) to see whether
it fits into a class (the disease or syndrome proposed as the hypothetical
diagnosis). For the second, our perspective is reversed, and we examine the
class to see whether the attributes of the class (diagnostic criteria) are
congruent with the particular case (the illness).
Inductive
reasoning complements this process by allowing the physician, through the
systematic performance of diagnostic tests in different patients, to observe
how different combinations of signs and symptoms are repeatedly associated with
certain diseases. Thus, abstraction and generalization arise not only from
clinical observation but also from the inductive interpretation of positive or
negative results of specific tests according to the case. It involves
abstracting findings, sowing clinical observations, and discerning what is
common among what is diverse.
Jorge
Luis Borges, in his short story Funes the
Memorious, describes a main character who lacks this capacity for
reasoning: “I suspect, nevertheless, that
he was not very capable of thought. To think is to forget a difference, to
generalize, to abstract. In Funes’
crowded world there were only details, almost immediate,” thereby
illustrating the epistemological importance of the ability to relativize and
contextualize details in order to think in general terms. This is essential to
build clinical judgment, identify patterns, and derive a diagnosis from the
integration of multiple data.6
Figures 1 and 2 depict the path from test questions to proof or refutation. It is
immediately evident that a highly specific test is used
primarily to confirm a disease. Specificity measures a test’s ability to
correctly identify people who do not have the disease, thus avoiding false
positives. If a test is highly specific and yields a positive result, it is
very likely that the person actually has the disease, so the positive
predictive value is high. Conversely, sensitive tests are used to rule out
diseases, because they have a high capacity to detect people who do have the
disease, thereby avoiding false negatives. It is also evident from Figures 1 and 2 that, on certain occasions, the
physician may end up with neither confirmation nor refutation of the
presumptive diagnosis in a strict logical sense.
Figure 3 indicates the relationship that may exist between a manifestation
and a disease. A manifestation may be associated with a
disease all the time (as a sine qua non condition), most of the time,
occasionally, or never. Unlike deduction, induction does not provide logical
certainties but clinical probabilities, so it must be complemented by
statistical evidence and by linked, consecutive testing. Despite its
relativity, it is essential for creating diagnostic criteria in daily practice.
REFUTING THE DIAGNOSIS BY
INCOMPATIBLE FINDINGS
If the
case presents incongruent features that cannot be explained in terms of the
hypothetical diagnosis, then that differential diagnosis must be discarded. For
example, if a patient presents with shoulder pain but lacks clinical
manifestations (M1) considered fundamental (or sine qua non), such as
asymmetric loss of shoulder abduction, shoulder-girdle atrophy, or scapular
dyskinesia, we could initially rule out facioscapulohumeral muscular dystrophy,
even if there is a hereditary history of this disease (Figure 4).
However,
the physician need not terminally reject the hypothetical diagnosis when
encountering an unexpected manifestation. The unforeseen manifestation may be
caused by a disease other than that indicated by the hypothetical diagnosis.
This additional clinical manifestation may represent another synchronous
disease, as can occur in a C5 radiculopathy coexisting with rotator cuff
syndrome (Figure 5). If the manifestation
can be attributed neither to the hypothetical diagnosis nor to a coexisting
synchronous diagnosis, the physician should consider a new hypothetical
diagnosis.
Beyond
this clinical scenario, ideally multiple independent diagnoses should be
avoided whenever possible because they compromise logical simplicity. The more
complicated the hypothesis, the more difficult it is to verify its probability.
This is known as the logical dictum of Ockham’s razor. In the nineteenth
century, Sir William Hamilton reformulated this principle as the “law of
parsimony,” which forbids, without proven necessity, the multiplication of
entities, powers, principles, or causes. Its best-known formulation is Entia non sunt multipli-canda praeter
necessitatem—entities are not to be multiplied without necessity—since
simple theories are easier to prove
or refute because they involve fewer variables and logical steps.7 This makes errors, if present, easier to detect.
In science, the capacity to refute a hypothesis is crucial. Therefore, although
the simplest explanation is not always the correct one, simple models prevail
over more complex ones.
Nevertheless,
in older patients or those with prior conditions, Ockham’s razor may lead to
excessive simplification of clinical interpretation, premature diagnostic
conclusions, and potentially suboptimal care.8
PROVING THE DIAGNOSIS BY CONGRUENT
FINDINGS
To claim
a definitive diagnosis on the grounds that it could explain all the findings is
to commit a logical fallacy: affirming the consequent.9 For example, “If the supraspinatus tendon
is completely torn, then the patient will have pain. If the patient has
shoulder pain, it is because the supraspinatus tendon is completely torn.”
There are many other causes of shoulder pain unrelated to the rotator cuff, and
the prevalence of supraspinatus tendon lesions in asymptomatic individuals is
high, so this reasoning is false.
A
diagnosis is proven only when the clinical findings, considered as a whole, are
attributable exclusively to the hypothetical diagnosis and to no other disease.
Unfortunately, few clinical findings are pathognomonic; otherwise, the
diagnostic process would be straightforward. For instance, the combination of
mechanical pain with nocturnal worsening and loss of active mobility does not
confirm rotator cuff syndrome.
When
there is no single pathognomonic finding, such as a
Popeye sign attributable to a lesion of the long head of the biceps, a
combination of findings considered together may serve the same function. While
a single clinical manifestation may not be
pathognomonic, the combination may be specific to a condition. This is the rule
in most clinical presentations and their corresponding
diseases (Figure 6).
ARE THE EXPECTED FINDINGS PRESENT?
Refuting the diagnosis by absence of
the expected findings
Can the combination of clinical manifestations that
characterizes the hypothetical diagnosis be found in the case at hand? Refutation of a diagnosis by failure to find an
expected finding is logically valid only if the expected finding is always
present in the disease in question, as in a sine
qua non condition. For example, a patient with a history of a bicycle fall
who has pain at the distal end of the clavicle but no “key-sign” deformity will
not have a complete injury of the coracoclavicular and acromioclavicular
ligaments, since the presence of that deformity is a sine qua non feature of
Rockwood grade 3, 4, and 5 acromioclavicular dislocations.10
PROVING THE DIAGNOSIS BY THE PRESENCE
OF THE EXPECTED FINDINGS
It is
logically false to claim that a diagnosis has been proven simply because the
expected manifestations are present. The claim requires that the combination of
manifestations be unique; otherwise, the fallacy of affirming the consequent
has been committed, as discussed above.
If a
disease always causes a given clinical finding, then that manifestation (sine qua non) must be present or the
diagnosis is refuted. But the presence of a sine qua non manifestation does not
prove the diagnosis. Proof requires that the findings be unique
(pathognomonic), not merely essential. A manifestation that is only sometimes
found in association with a disease may be used to affirm its presence if that
manifestation meets the prerequisite of uniqueness. Such a finding could be,
for example, calcific tendinopathy of the rotator cuff in a patient with
shoulder pain.
Experience
(and inductive inference) does not yield judgments with true and strict
universality, but rather with assumed and relative generalization. In this
sense, evidence-based medicine offers statistical and therefore probabilistic
knowledge. The frequency with which particular manifestations associate with a
disease does have affirmative value. If we find manifestations with a high
statistical association with the hypothesized diagnosis, our argument is
stronger than if the manifestations are rarely associated. The more such
manifestations we identify, the more confidently we may affirm the diagnosis.
For example, in a patient with diabetes and hypothyroidism, the likelihood of
frozen shoulder is much higher if sudden, atraumatic pain is associated with a
global loss of mobility.11
The ideal
clinical manifestations to validate our diagnostic hypothesis will be those
that, taken together, are highly specific and statistically associated with the
disease. If we select a group of manifestations with these attributes, we will
have developed diagnostic criteria. As noted, this is achieved through pattern
recognition, categorization, and hypothesis testing. If we fail to achieve
certainty through this method, we must persist in the search rather than deny
contradictory evidence in order to choose an unrealistic hypothesis.
CONCLUSIONS
Medical
diagnosis is a complex process. To accomplish it, physicians employ logic,
knowledge, and experience through the hypothesis method, which consists of
choosing the best explanation among several alternatives. This method is
grounded in critical thinking, applied in medicine as clinical reasoning.
The
diagnostic process combines three modes of reasoning: abductive, deductive, and
inductive. Abductive reasoning allows hypotheses to be formulated from
incomplete and dynamic observations, establishing possible explanations based
on conditional probability. Deductive reasoning then evaluates which tests
would confirm or refute the hypothesis, eliminating incorrect diagnoses.
Finally, inductive reasoning analyzes whether the clinical findings match the
hypothesized diagnosis.
Diagnostic
errors may arise from overreliance on pattern recognition without considering
exceptions or from ignoring logical fallacies. The objectivity of scientific
evidence is key to avoiding misdiagnosis. Diagnostic error is not inevitable,
and accuracy improves with the proper use of logic, scientific evidence, and
systematic patient evaluation.
1. Ledley
RS, Lusted LB. Reasoning foundations of medical diagnosis. MD Comput 1991;8(5):300-15. PMID:
1749340
2. Sooknanan
J, Seemungal T. Not so elementary - the reasoning behind a medical diagnosis. MedEdPublish (2016) 2019;8:234. https://doi.org/10.15694/mep.2019.000234.1
3. Platón. Fedón. Traducido por Luis Eggers Lan.
Madrid: Gredos; 2003.
4. Peirce
CS. Deduction, induction, and hypothesis. Popular
Science Monthly 1878;13:470-82. Disponible en: https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Popular_Science_Monthly/Volume_13/August_1878/Illustrations_of_the_Logic_of_Science_VI?
5. del Sel
JM. La lógica del descubrimiento
científico. Resonancias de fin de siglo. Buenos Aires: Editorial La Balsa;
1999.
6. Borges
JL. Funes el memorioso. En: Borges JL. Ficciones.
Buenos Aires: Editorial Sur; 1944, p. 93-103.
7. Hamilton
W. Discussions on philosophy and
literature, education and university reform. London: Longman, Brown, Green,
and Longmans; 1852.
8. Redelmeier
DA, Shafir E. The fallacy of a single diagnosis. Med Decis Making 2023;43(2):183-90. https://doi.org/10.1177/0272989X221121343
9. Frye AM,
Levi WA. Rational belief. New York:
Harcourt, Brace, and Co.; 1941, p. 297-99.
10. Rockwood
CA Jr. Fractures and dislocations of the shoulder. En: Rockwood CA Jr, Green DP
(ed.). Fractures in adults.
Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott; 1984, p. 860-910.
11. Ananda
Rao A, Awale M, Davis S. Medical diagnosis reimagined as a process of bayesian
reasoning and elimination. Cureus
2023;15(9):e45097. https://doi.org/10.7759/cureus.45097
D. Moya ORCID ID: https://orcid.org/0000-0003-1889-7699
Received on February 20th,
2025. Accepted after evaluation on June 17th, 2025 •
Dr. Federico Alfano • drfedericoalfano@gmail.com
• https://orcid.org/0000-0003-1078-2600
How to
cite this article: Alfano F, Moya D. The Logic of Clinical Reasoning in
Medicine. Rev Asoc Argent Ortop Traumatol
2025;90(4):396-404. https://doi.org/10.15417/issn.1852-7434.2025.90.4.2127
Article
Info
Identification: https://doi.org/10.15417/issn.1852-7434.2025.90.4.2127
Published: August, 2025
Conflict
of interests: The authors declare no conflicts of interest.
Copyright: © 2025, Revista de la Asociación Argentina de
Ortopedia y Traumatología.
License:
This article is under Attribution-NonCommertial-ShareAlike 4.0 International
Creative Commons License (CC-BY-NC-SA 4.0).